(LifeSiteNews) — Human beings have a natural tendency to obey those who exercise authority.
This tendency clearly manifests itself from the earliest stages of childhood. Children have a natural tendency to obey their parents and to internalize their commands and expectations.
Adults too, tend to conform to what is expected of them. Most people feel most comfortable when they are obeying the laws and accepted customs of their society. Social conformity is the norm for human beings, even when a particular custom or practice is not mandated by law and has no criminal or civil penalties attached. Most people simply want to fit in.
There is a positive and a negative side to his tendency.
The positive side is that it is necessary and healthy for children, whose rational faculties have not yet developed, to be obedient to their parents and to learn from them how they should behave.
It is also necessary for adult humans, who have to live together peacefully in society, to obey the laws, even at the cost of personal benefit or convenience.
No state could fulfil its role of attaining the common good, if the members of a society refused to submit to its legitimate authority or to obey the laws made for the good of the community. Furthermore, man, in his fallen human nature, often needs some form of external coercion to prevent him from committing actions harmful to the common good.
There are also negative consequences to man’s tendency to conform to accepted laws and customs.
When those in power impose unjust laws, many people will go along with those laws, and accept docilely what they would have previously opposed. And they may go beyond mere external conformity to the law, and actually change their internal disposition.
For example, many people not only tolerate abortion and but even think that it “must be OK” because “it’s not against the law.”
Similarly, many people will quickly adapt to dominant social norms. In the 1960s, for example, there was a radical change in what was regarded as morally acceptable by the majority.
It is clear then that those who hold power in a society, whether it be the power to change laws or the power to influence social norms, how the capacity to lead society away from the common good very quickly.
Those who possess political power and influence are able to “weaponize” our natural tendency to obey laws and follows customs, in a way which subverts the real purpose of that tendency, which is the common good of society.
In order to guard against this, it is important to have a very clear idea of what law is, and when a law must be obeyed. Fortunately, St. Thomas Aquinas treats of this question with great clarity in the Summa Theologica. The rest of this article will summarise his teaching.
What is law?
St. Thomas Aquinas gives the following as a complete definition of law. A law is “an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and promulgated.”[1]
Everything that conforms to this definition is a law. Nothing contrary to this definition can ever be a true law, no matter what the purported lawgiver may claim.
I will examine each element of the above definition in more detail, but first I will briefly describe the four kinds of laws.
The four kinds of law
St. Thomas teaches that there are four kinds of law.
- The eternal law: by this law God governs “the whole community of the universe” by His “Divine Reason” and “Divine Providence.” St. Thomas teaches that “the very idea of the government of things in God the Ruler of the universe, has the nature of a law.”[2] All creation is subject to the eternal law: “all things partake somewhat of the eternal law, in so far as, namely, from its being imprinted on them, they derive their respective inclinations to their proper acts and ends.”[3]
- The natural law: the “participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is called the natural law.”[4] By this law, imprinted on every human being, we are directed towards our proper natural ends: “the light of natural reason, whereby we discern what is good and what is evil, which is the function of the natural law, is nothing else than an imprint on us of the Divine light.”[5]
- The human law: while the natural law directs us in “a general and indeterminate” way, it is often necessary for human happiness for legitimate authority to make “more particular determination of certain matters.”[6] For example, while the natural law is sufficient for us to know that we shouldn’t kill others by poisoning, human law may provide more precise regulations on how dangerous substances must be handled. All human law is derived from the principles of the natural law.[7]
- The divine law: this has been revealed by God to direct us to our supernatural end. St Thomas gives four reasons why a divinely revealed law is necessary:
-
The natural law directs us to natural happiness but not to supernatural happiness[8]
-
Our human judgement can suffer from “uncertainty… especially on contingent and particular matters… therefore, that man may know without any doubt what he ought to do and what he ought to avoid, it was necessary for man to be directed in his proper acts by a law given by God, for it is certain that such a law cannot err.”[9]
-
Human laws can only regulate external acts. Yet virtue requires also interior acts. Therefore, God commands these internal acts through the divine law.[10]
-
Human law cannot punish all human acts, “since while aiming at doing away with all evils, it would do away with many good things, and would hinder the advance of the common good.”[11] “In order, therefore, that no evil might remain unforbidden and unpunished, it was necessary for the Divine law to supervene, whereby all sins are forbidden.”[12]
All four forms of law conform entirely to the definition of law given by St. Thomas, namely that law is “an ordinance of reason for the common good, made by him who has care of the community, and promulgated.”[13]
I will now examine each part of the definition in more detail, but with emphasis on its implications for laws promulgated by human beings. The eternal law, the natural law and the divine law are all promulgated by God Himself, for the common good, and in accordance with His Eternal Reason.[14]
A law is an ordinance of reason
“Law,” states St. Thomas, “is a rule and measure of acts, whereby man is induced to act or is restrained from acting,” consequently “it belongs to the law to command and to forbid.”[15]
All truly human acts must accord with reason.[16] Therefore laws, which induce man to act or restrain him from acting, must also accord with reason.[17]
No command contrary to reason can have the nature of law:
[I]n order that the volition of what is commanded may have the nature of law, it needs to be in accord with some rule of reason.[18]
Furthermore, as stated above, human law is derived from the natural law, “consequently every human law has just so much of the nature of law, as it is derived from the law of nature. But if in any point it deflects from the law of nature, it is no longer a law but a perversion of law.”[19]
A law is ordained to the common good
Laws are always directed to the common good of the community for which they are ordained, whether that be the Church or the state. And the primary end of every law must be the end of human life itself, namely happiness; “the law must needs regard principally the relationship to happiness.”[20] Those civil laws called “just” are those “which are adapted to produce and preserve happiness and its parts for the body politic.”[21]
It follows from this that any command which is contrary to the common good, does not have the nature of law:
Consequently, since the law is chiefly ordained to the common good, any other precept in regard to some individual work, must needs be devoid of the nature of a law, save in so far as it regards the common good.[22]
A law is made by legitimate authority
Laws are directed to the common good. Therefore, only the whole community, or those with legitimate authority over the whole community, can make laws.
As St. Thomas teaches:
Now to order anything to the common good, belongs either to the whole people, or to someone who is the viceregent of the whole people. And therefore the making of a law belongs either to the whole people or to a public personage who has care of the whole people: since in all other matters the directing of anything to the end concerns him to whom the end belongs.[23]
If a private person – someone who does not have legitimate authority – tries to make or enforce a law this is null and void.[24]
The force of laws passed by legitimate authority is diminished – and perhaps made entirely null – if the laws they pass are contrary to the universal custom of a people:
[T]o a certain extent, the mere change of law is of itself prejudicial to the common good: because custom avails much for the observance of laws, seeing that what is done contrary to general custom, even in slight matters, is looked upon as grave. Consequently, when a law is changed, the binding power of the law is diminished, in so far as custom is abolished.
Wherefore human law should never be changed, unless, in some way or other, the common weal be compensated according to the extent of the harm done in this respect. Such compensation may arise either from some very great and every evident benefit conferred by the new enactment; or from the extreme urgency of the case, due to the fact that either the existing law is clearly unjust, or its observance extremely harmful. Wherefore the jurist says that ‘in establishing new laws, there should be evidence of the benefit to be derived, before departing from a law which has long been considered just.’
Indeed, custom itself can have force of law:
Augustine says ‘The customs of God’s people and the institutions of our ancestors are to be considered as laws. And those who throw contempt on the customs of the Church ought to be punished as those who disobey the law of God.’[25]
Furthermore, if a people are:
[F]ree, and able to make their own laws, the consent of the whole people expressed by a custom counts far more in favour of a particular observance, that does the authority of the sovereign, who has not the power to frame laws, except as representing the people.[26]
A law is duly promulgated
Laws by their nature are made for the good of a particular community. Therefore, they must be duly applied to that community to have the nature of law.
As St. Thomas states:
Wherefore, in order that a law obtain the binding force which is proper to a law, it must needs be applied to the men who have to be ruled by it. Such application is made by its being notified to them by promulgation. Wherefore promulgation is necessary for the law to obtain its force.[27]
The manner of promulgation will differ from society to society.
Do we have to obey an unjust law?
In general, we are bound obey true laws:
If they be just, they have the power of binding in conscience, from the eternal law whence they are derived, according to Proverbs 8:15: ‘By Me kings reign, and lawgivers decree just things.’[28]
There will of course be certain circumstances in which even true laws are not binding, for example, laws cease to bind if their application becomes harmful:
Now it happens often that the observance of some point of law conduces to the common weal in the majority of instances, and yet, in some cases, is very hurtful. Since then the lawgiver cannot have in view every single case, he shapes the law according to what happens most frequently, by directing his attention to the common good. Wherefore if a case arise wherein the observance of that law would be hurtful to the general welfare, it should not be observed.[29]
But what of laws that do not fulfil the definition of true law?
St. Thomas separates these into two categories.
- “Laws” that are contrary to the “divine law,” such as a law which commands something sinful; “laws of this kind must nowise be observed, because, as stated in Acts 5:29, ‘we ought to obey God rather than man.’”[30]
- “Laws” that are contrary to a “human good,” but which do not command something intrinsically evil. These “laws” are also unjust and “a law that is not just, seems to be no law at all.” They are “acts of violence rather than laws.” Consequently “such laws do not bind in conscience,” except perhaps in certain individual circumstances, “in order to avoid scandal or disturbance.”[31]
Conclusions
Any purported law, which either (a) is contrary to reason, (b) is contrary to the common good of the community for which it is made, (c) is made by an individual lacking legitimate authority or (d) is not duly promulgated, is null and void and has no binding effect.
In the light of this we can that many purported laws are certainly not true laws. No law which permits abortion, or euthanasia, or any other morally unacceptable act, can be considered a true law.
Similarly, laws which harm the common good – such as laws mandating lockdowns – are to be regarded as “acts of violence” rather than laws, and therefore “do not bind in conscience.”
Armed with this understanding we will be better able to resist the misuse of “law” by those who seek to undermine the common good of society.
References
↑1 | St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, II. I q.90 a.4. |
---|---|
↑2 | II. I q.91 a.1. |
↑3 | II. I q.91 a.2. |
↑4 | II. I q.91 a.2 |
↑5 | II. I q.91 a.2 |
↑6 | II. I q.91 a.3 |
↑7 | II. I q.95. a.2 |
↑8 | II. I q.91 a.4 |
↑9 | II. I q.91 a.4 |
↑10 | II. I q.91 a.4 |
↑11 | II. I q.91 a.4 |
↑12 | II. I q.91 a.4 |
↑13 | II. I q.90 a.4 |
↑14 | II. I q.91 a.1-4 |
↑15 | II.I q.90 a.1 |
↑16 | II. I q.1 a.1 |
↑17 | II.I q.90 a.1 |
↑18 | II.I q.90 a.1 |
↑19 | II. I q.95. a.2 |
↑20 | II. I. q.90 a.2 |
↑21 | II. I. q.90 a.2 |
↑22 | II. I. q.90 a.2 |
↑23 | II. I. q.90 a.3 |
↑24 | II. I. q.90 a.3 |
↑25 | II.I q.97 a.3 |
↑26 | II.I q.97 a.3 |
↑27 | II. I. q.90 a.4 |
↑28 | II.I q.96. a |
↑29 | I.I q.96 a.6 |
↑30 | II. I. q.96 a.4 |
↑31 | II. I. q.96 a.4 |